The Role of the Heretic
by Isaac Asimov
(First appeared as the Foreward to Scientists Confront Velikovsky, 1977, Cornell University Press)
What
does one do with a heretic? We know the
answer if the “one” referred to is a powerful religious orthodoxy: the heretic
can be burned at the stake. If the “one”
is a powerful political orthodoxy, there heretic can be sent to a concentration
camp. If the “one” is a powerful
socioeconomic orthodoxy, the heretic can be prevented from earning a living.
But what
if the “one” is a powerful scientific orthodoxy? In that case, very little can be done,
because even the most powerful scientific orthodoxy is not very powerful. To be sure, if the heretic is himself a
scientist and depends on some organized scientific pursuit for his living or
for his renown, things can be made hard for him. He can be deprived of government grants, of
prestige-filled appointments, of access to the learned journals. This is bad enough, and not lightly to be
condoned, but it is peanuts compared to the punishments that could be, and
sometimes are, visited on heretics by other orthodoxies.
Then,
too, the religious, political, and socioeconomic orthodoxies can be universal
in their power. A religious orthodoxy in
full flight visits its punishments not on priests alone; nor a political one on
politicians alone; nor a socioeconomic one on society leaders alone. No one is immune to their displeasure. The scientific orthodoxy, however, is
completely helpless if the heretic is not himself a professional scientist—if
he does not depend on grants or appointments, and if he places his views before
the world through some medium other than the learned journals. Therefore, if we are to consider scientific
heretics, we must understand that there are two varieties with different powers
and different immunities.
Let us
consider the two kinds of scientific heretics: (1) There are those who arise
from within the professional world of science and who are subject to punishment
by the orthodoxy. We might call these
heretics from within “endoheretics”. (2)
There are those who arise from outside the professional world of science and
who are immune to direct punishment by the orthodoxy. These heretics from without are the
“exoheretics.”
Of the
two, the endoheretics are far less well known to the general public. The endoheretics speaks in the same language
as does the orthodoxy, and both views, the endoheretical and the orthodox, are
equally obscure to the nonscientist, who can, generally speaking, understand
neither the one nor the other nor the nature of the conflict between them.
It
follows that if we consider the great endoheresies of the past, we find that
the general public was not ordinarily involved.
In the few cases where the public was involved, it was almost invariably
on the side of the orthodoxy. The patron
saint of all scientific heresies, Galileo, was, of course, an endoheretic. He was deeply versed in Aristotelian physics
and Ptolemaic astronomy, which he dethroned, as were any of his
Aristotelian/Ptolemaic opponents. And
since in those days and in his particularly society, the scientific and
religious orthodoxies were the same, Galileo had to run far greater risks than
later endoheretics did. Facing the
Inquisition, he had to consider the possibility, not of a canceled grant, but
of physical torture. Yet we cannot
suppose that there was any great popular outcry on behalf of the rebel. The general public was not concerned, nor
even aware, of the dispute. Had it been
made aware, it would certainly have sided with the
orthodoxy.
Next to
Galileo, the greatest of the endoheretics was Charles Darwin, whose views on
the evolution of species through the blind action of chance variation and
natural selection turned biology upside down.
Here, the general public did know of the controversy and did,
in a very general and rough way, have a dim view of what it was about. And the public was definitely
on the side of the orthodoxy. The
public has remained antievolution to this day.
Science has accepted Darwin without, up to this time, respectable
dissent. The more sophisticated churches
no longer quarrel publicly with Darwin’s views.
But the general public, in what is probably majority opinion if a vote
were to be taken, stubbornly adheres to the tents of a lot and dead orthodoxy
of a century and a quarter ago.
Galileo
and Darwin won out. Along the way, a number of the endoheretics did win. But never by public pressure. And never by a majority vote of the general
public. They won out because science is
a self-correcting structure, and because observation, experimentation, and
reasoning eventually support those heresies which represent a more accurate
view of the Universe and bury those orthodoxies which are outpaced. In the process, orthodoxy gets a bad
press. Looking back on the history of
science, we might suppose that every endoheretics was right—that each wore the
white hat of heroism against an evil and short-sighted orthodoxy. But that is only because the history of
science is naturally selective. Only the
endoheretics who was, in the end, shown to be right makes his mark. For each of those, there may have been
perhaps fifty endoheretics who were quite wrong, whose views are therefore
scarcely remembered, and who are not recorded even as a footnote in the history
books—or, if they are, it is for other, nonheretical, work.
What,
then, would you have the orthodox do? Is
it better to reject everything and be wrong once in fifty times—or accept
everything and be wrong forty-nine out of fifty times and, in the meantime,
send science down endless blind alleys?
The best strategy, of course, would be neither, but to reject the
forty-nine wrong out of hand and to accept and cherish the one right. Unfortunately, the day that the endoheretical
pearl shines out so obviously amid the endoheretical garbage as to be easily
plucked is the day of the millennium.
There is, alas, no easy way of distinguishing the stroke of the
intuitional genius from the stroke of folly.
In fact, many an utterly nonsensical suggestion has seemed to carry much
more of the mark of truth than the cleverly insightful stroke of genius.
There is
no way, then, of dealing with the endoheresies other than by a firm (but not
blind or spiteful) opposition. Each must
run the gauntlet that alone can test it.
For the
self-correcting structure works. There
is delay and heartbreak often enough, but it works. However grim and slow the self-questioning
process of science may be (indeed, that the process exists at all is a matter
of pride to scientists), science remains man’s only self-correcting
intellectual endeavor.
The
problem of endoheresy, then, is not a truly serious one for science (though it
may be, we all know, for the individual endoheretic); and the questioning
process is not one which must be carried out in public.
But what
of exoheresy?
We had
better first be sure of what we mean by an exoheretic. Science is split into endless specialties,
and a specialist who is narrow-minded and insecure may see anyone who is not
bull’s-eye on target within the specialty as an “outsider”.
Robert
Mayer was a physician and James P. Joule was a brewer who dabbled in
physics. Neither had academic
credentials, and, while both of them recognized the
existence of the law of conservation of energy, their observations went for
nothing. Neither could get his views
accepted. Hermann Helmholtz, third in
line, was a full academician, and he gets the credit.
When Jacobus
van’t Hoff worked out the scheme of the tetravalent
carbon atom, the orthodox chemist Adolph Kolbe denounced the new concept intemperately,
specifically and contemptuously mentioning the fact that van’t
Hoff was teaching at a veterinary school.
But this
kind of attitude won’t do. If we wish to
be fine enough and narrow enough, then all scientific heretics are exoheretics
in the eyes of the sufficiently orthodox, and the term becomes
meaningless. Nor should we label as
exoheretics those who are not formally educated but who, through
self-education, have reached the peak of professional excellence. Let us, instead, understand the word exoheretic
to refer only to someone who is a real outsider, one who does not understand
the painstaking structure built up by science, and who therefore attacks it
without understanding.
The
typical exoheretic is so unaware of the intimate structure of science, of the
methods and philosophy o f science, of the very
language of science, that his views are virtually unintelligible from the scientific
standpoint. As a
consequence, he is generally ignored by scientists. If exoheretical views are forced upon
scientists, the reaction is bound to be puzzlement or amusement or contempt. In any case, it would be exceptional if the
exoheresy were deemed worthy of any sort of comment.
In
frustration, the exoheretic is very likely to appeal over the heads of the
scientists to the general public. He may
even be successful in this, since his inability to speak the language of
science does not necessarily prevent him from speaking the language of the
public. The appeal to the public is, of
course, valueless from the scientific standpoint. The findings of science cannot be canceled or
reversed by majority vote, or by the highest legislative or executive
fiat. If every government in the world
declared, officially, that the Earth is flat, and if every scientist were
forbidden to argue the contrary, the Earth would nevertheless remain
spheroidal, and every scrap of evidence maintaining that conclusion would still
exist.
Nevertheless,
the appeal to the public has other rewards than that of establishing scientific
proof. (1) A favorable public response
is soul-satisfying. The exoheretic can
easily convince himself that his position at the center of a cult demonstrates
the value of his views. He can easily
argue himself into believing that people would not flock to nonsense, though
all history shows otherwise. (2) A
favorable public response can be lucrative.
It is well known that books and lectures dealing favorably with a
popular cult do far better than do books and lectures debunking it, even when
the books in favor may be poorly written and reasoned, whereas the books
against may be models of lucidity and rationality. (3) A favorable public response may hound
scientists into open opposition, and they may express, with injudicious force,
their opinion of the obvious nonsense of the exoheretical views. This very opposition, casting the exoheretic
into the role of martyr, works to accentuate the first two advantages.
Public
support or no, the exoheretic virtually never proves to be right. (How can he be right when he, quite
literally, doesn’t know what he’s talking about?) Of course, he may prove to have said
something somewhere in this flood of words that bears some resemblance to
something that later proves to be so, and this coincidental concurrence of word
and fact may be hailed by his followers as proving all the rest of the corpus
of his work. This outcome, however, has
only cultic value.
We see,
then, the vast difference between the effects of the views of endoheretics and
exoheretics. First, the public is generally
not interested in the endoheretic, or, if aware of him at all, is hostile to
him. The endoheretic therefore rarely
profits from his heresy in any material way.[1] The public, on the other hand, can be very
interested in the exoheretic and can support him with a partisan and even
religious fervor, so that the exoheretic may, in a material way, profit very
considerably by his heresy.
Second,
the endoheretic is sometimes right, and since startling scientific advances
usually begin as heresies, some of the greatest names in science have been
endoheretics. The exoheretic, on the
other hand, is virtually never right, and the history of science contains no
great advance, to my knowledge, initiated by an exoheretic.
One
might combine these generalizations and, working backward (not always a safe
procedure), state that when a view denounced by scientists as false is,
nevertheless, popular with the general public, the mere fact of that popularity
is strong evidence in favor of its worthlessness. It is on the basis of public popularity of
particular beliefs, for instance, that I, even without personal investigation
of such matters, feel it safe to be extremely skeptical about ancient
astronauts, or about modern astronauts in UFO’s, or about the value of talking to
plants, or about psi phenomena, or about spiritualism, or about astrology.[2]
And this
brings me to Velikovskianism at last.
Of all
the exoheretics, Velikovsky has come closest to discomfiting the science he has
attacked, and has most successfully forced science to
take him seriously. Why is that? Well—
1.
Velikovsky
has been a psychiatrist, so that he has training in a scientific specialty of
sorts and is not an utter exoheretic. What’s
more, he has the faculty of sounding as though he knows what he is talking
about when he invades the precincts of astronomy. He doesn’t make very many elementary
mistakes, and he is able to use the language of science sufficiently well to
impress a layman.
2.
He
is an interesting writer. It’s fun to
read his books. I have read every book
he has published and hope to read any he writes in the future. Although he doesn’t lure me into accepting
his views, I can well see where those less knowledgeable in the fields
Velikovsky deals with would succumb.
3.
Velikovsky’s
views in Worlds in Collision are designed to demonstrate that the Bible
has a great deal of literal truth in it, that the miraculous events described
in the Old Testament really happened as described. To be sure, Velikovsky abandons the
hypothesis that divine intervention caused the miracles and substitutes a far
less satisfactory hypothesis involving planetary Ping-Pong, but that scarcely
alters the fact that in our theistic society any claimed finding that tends to
demonstrate the truth of the Bible is highly likely to meet with general favor.
These three points are
enough in themselves to explain Velikovsky’s popularity. Supply the public with something amusing,
that sounds scholarly, and that supports an idea it wants to believe, and
surely you need nothing more. Erich von Daniken and his theories of ancient astronauts have
succeeded on little more than this, even though his books are less amusing than
Velikovsky’s, sound less scholarly, and support something less substantial than
belief in the Bible.
Velikovsky, however, has
succeeded beyond such popularity. Because
of the climate of the times when Worlds in Collision was published,
there was an astronomical overreaction.
The appearance of excerpts from this book, prior to publication, in Harper’s,
Reader’s Digest, and Collier’s, and the widespread publicity given to
his views, goaded some astronomers into an attempt at censorship. To paraphrase Fouché,
this was worse than immoral; it was a blunder.
The fact
that Velikovsky could then portray himself as a persecuted martyr has cast a
Galilean glow upon all his endeavors, and has canceled
out any attempt on the part of the astronomers to demonstrate, clearly and
dispassionately, the errors in the Velikovskian
view. All attempts in this direction can
be (and are) dismissed as persecution.
It also
gives a glow of heroism to Velikovsky’s followers. They can attack an orthodoxy—ordinarily such
attacks are accepted as courageous—and can do so with complete safety, since in
actual fact (as opposed to Velikovskian
fantasy) the orthodoxy does not, and indeed cannot, strike back.
From the
standpoint of science, is Velikovskianism nothing but
an irritation and a waste of time? Not
at all. It has enormous benefits. For one thing, Velikovskianism,
and indeed, any exoheretical view that becomes prominent enough to force itself
on science, acts to puncture scientific complacency—and that is good. An exoheresy may cause scientists to bestir
themselves for the purpose of re-examining the bases of their beliefs, even if
only to gather firm and logical reasons for the rejection of the exoheresy—and that
is good, too. An exoheresy may cause
scientific activity which, in serendipitous fashion, may uncover something
worthwhile that has nothing to do with the exoheresy—and that is very good, if
it happens. The Fates keep science from
remaining unchallenged. Science is in
far greater danger from the absence of challenge than from the coming of any
number of even absurd challenges.
At the
American Association for the Advancement of Science meeting in 1974, scientists
as a group responded to Velikovsky’s exoheretical challenge for the first
time. Four of the five essays in this
book were prepared for and read at that meeting for other scientists and are
now published in slightly revised form for the general public. For reasons explained in Donald Goldsmith’s
Introduction, the papers by Velikovsky and Irving Michelson do not appear in
this book.
It was altogether
fitting and proper that Velikovsky and his opponents agreed to hold this
discussion at the AAAS meetings. Though
one could be sure from the start that nothing scientists could say would in the
least move the Velikovskians, and that no amount of
mere logic would shake their faith, it was still a good thing—for science.
[1] I must qualify these generalizations because there are exceptions, of course. Edward Jenner, who advanced the endoheretical technique of smallpox vaccination, was accepted eagerly by the public, and profited materially as a result.
[2] Of course, I would also have used this line of reasoning to feel it safe to be skeptical about the value of smallpox vaccination, but the facts would have converted within a year in that case.